I'm still studying Hilary Putnam and related works and don't expect to reach any firm conclusions for some time. Some of Putnam's essays are quite difficult. There is an interesting and (for me) hard to define tension between Putnam's philosophy and the marxist philosophy of
ascending from the abstract to the concrete (link to a 2006 blog about that).
Here is a very rough summary:
- the copy theory of truth is not valid (the idea that our minds and hence our words represent some sort of mirror copy of the real world is not valid)
- Subjective or relativist views are not valid (eg. post modernist and / or Kuhnian views that what we regard as "truth" depends on the perspective of the observer)
- We approach the truth through being rational
- Rationality includes both facts and values (eg. beauty is rational and that is factual)
- let the Hegelian metaphor be: the mind and the world jointly make up the mind and the world
- it's important to break down the socially ingrained fact / value dichotomy
- the "scientific idea" of One True Theory does not hold up
Reason, Truth and History by Hilary Putnam (the link is to a full copy available from Brewster Kahle's Internet Archive)
Preface
In the present work, the aim which I have in mind is to break the
strangle hold which a number of dichotomies appear to have on
the thinking of both philosophers and laymen. Chief among
these is the dichotomy between objective and subjective views of
truth and reason. The phenomenon I am thinking of is this: once
such a dichotomy as
the dichotomy between 'objective' and 'subjective' has become accepted, accepted not as a mere pair of categories but as a characterization of types of views and styles of
thought, thinkers
begin to view the terms of the dichotomy
almost as ideological labels. Many, perhaps most, philosophers
hold some version of
the 'copy' theory of truth today, the conception according to which a statement is true just in case it
'corresponds to the (mind independent) facts'; and the philosophers in this faction see the only alternative as the denial of the
objectivity of truth and a capitulation to the idea that all schemes
of thought and all points of view are hopelessly subjective. Inevitably a bold minority (Kuhn, in some of his moods at least;
Feyerabend, and such distinguished continental philosophers as
Foucault) range themselves under the opposite label. They agree
that the alternative to a naive copy conception of truth is to see
systems of thought, ideologies, even (in the case of Kuhn and
Feyerabend) scientific theories, as subjective, and they proceed
to put forward a relativist and subjective view with vigor.
That philosophical dispute assumes somewhat the character
of ideological dispute is not, of itself, necessarily bad: new ideas,
even in the most exact sciences, are frequently both espoused
and attacked with partisan vigor. Even in politics, polarization
and ideological fervor are sometimes necessary to bring moral
seriousness to an issue. But in time, both in philosophy and politics, new ideas become old ideas; what was once challenging,
becomes predictable and boring; and what once served to focus
attention where it should be focussed, later keeps discussion
from considering new alternatives. This has now happened in
the debate between the correspondence views of truth and subjectivist views. In the first three chapters of this book I shall try
to explain a conception of truth which unites objective and subjective components. This view, in spirit at least, goes back to
ideas of Immanuel Kant; and it holds that we can reject a naive
'copy' conception of truth without having to hold that it's all a
matter of the Zeitgeist, or a matter of 'gestalt switches', or all a
matter of ideology.
The view which I shall defend holds, to put it very roughly,
that there is an extremely close connection between the notions
of truth and rationality; that, to put it even more crudely,
the
only criterion for what is a fact is what it is rational to accept.
(I mean this quite literally and across the board; thus if it can be
rational to accept that a picture is beautiful, then it can be a fact
that the picture is beautiful.)
There can be value facts on this
conception. But the relation between rational acceptability and
truth is a relation between two distinct notions. A statement can
be rationally acceptable at a time but not true; and this realist
intuition will be preserved in my account.
I do not believe, however, that rationality is defined by a set of
unchanging 'canons' or 'principles'; methodological principles
are connected with our view of the world, including our view of
ourselves as part of the world, and change with time. Thus I
agree with the subjectivist philosophers that there is no fixed,
ahistorical organon which defines what it is to be rational; but I
don't conclude from the fact that our conceptions of reason
evolve in history, that reason itself can be (or evolve into) anything, nor do I end up in some fancy mixture of cultural relativism and 'structuralism' like the French philosophers. The dichotomy: either ahistorical unchanging canons of rationality or
cultural relativism is a dichotomy that I regard as outdated.
Another feature of the view is that rationality is not restricted
to laboratory science, nor different in a fundamental way in
laboratory science and outside of it. The conception that it is
seems to me a hangover from positivism; from the idea that the
scientific world is in some way constructed out of 'sense data'
and the idea that terms in the laboratory sciences are 'operationally defined'. I shall not devote much space to criticizing operationalist and positivist views of science; these have been thoroughly criticized in the last twenty-odd years. But
the empiricist
idea that 'sense data' constitute some sort of objective 'ground
floor' for at least a part of our knowledge will be reexamined in
the light of what we have to say about truth and rationality (in
Chapter 3).
In short, I shall advance a view in which the mind does not
simply 'copy' a world which admits of description by One True
Theory. But my view is not a view in which the mind makes up
the world, either (or makes it up subject to constraints imposed
by 'methodological canons' and mind-independent 'sense-data').
If one must use metaphorical language, then
let the metaphor be
this: the mind and the world jointly make up the mind and the
world. (Or, to make the metaphor even more Hegelian, the Universe makes up the Universe - with minds - collectively - playing a special role in the making up.)
A final feature of my account of rationality is this: I shall try
to show that our notion of rationality is, at bottom, just one part
of our conception of human flourishing, our idea of the good.
Truth is deeply dependent on what have been recently called
'values' (Chapter 6). And what we said above about rationality
and history also applies to value and history; there is no given,
ahistorical, set of 'moral principles' which define once and for
all what human flourishing consists in; but that doesn't mean
that it's all merely cultural and relative. Since the current state in
the theory of truth - the current dichotomy between copy theories of truth and subjective accounts of truth - is at least partly
responsible, in my view, for the notorious 'fact/value' dichotomy,
it is only by going to a very deep level and correcting our
accounts of truth and rationality themselves that we can get
beyond the fact/value dichotomy. (A dichotomy which, as it is
conventionally understood, virtually commits one to some sort
of relativism.) The current views of truth are alienated views;
they cause one to lose one part or another of one's self and the
world, to see the world as simply consisting of elementary particles swerving in the void (the 'physicalist' view, which sees the
scientific description as converging to the
One True Theory), or
to see the world as simply consisting of 'actual and possible
sense-data' (the older empiricist view), or to deny that there is a
world at all, as opposed to a bunch of stories that we make up
for various (mainly unconscious) reasons. And my purpose in
this work is to sketch the leading ideas of a non- alienated view.